Anaximander
Anaximander was a pre-Socratic philosopher from Miletus and a student of Thales, who is often regarded as the first philosopher in Western history. Renowned for his contributions to astronomy, geography, and philosophy, Anaximander is credited with creating one of the first maps of the world, which was centered on Delphi, and a celestial map that included a dynamic model of the cosmos. His philosophical work introduced the concept of the "apeiron," or the Boundless, as the eternal source of all things, challenging Thales' notion that a single element, like water, could serve as the origin of all existence. Anaximander's ideas emphasized a rational understanding of the universe, proposing that the cosmos operates under an intelligible order rather than chaotic forces. His theories suggested that opposites manifest through cyclical processes, contributing to a unified view of existence. Anaximander’s legacy is profound, as his pioneering approach laid the groundwork for future scientific inquiry and philosophical thought, influencing the development of models and maps that remain vital to modern science and navigation. His work represents a significant advancement in the understanding of nature, revealing a commitment to rational deduction and systematic observation.
On this Page
Subject Terms
Anaximander
Greek philosopher, astronomer, and cartographer
- Born: c. 610 b.c.e.
- Birthplace: Miletus, Greek Asia Minor (now in Turkey)
- Died: c. 547 b.c.e.
- Place of death: Probably Miletus (now in Turkey)
Anaximander invented the scientific use of models and maps. He also realized, contrary to the prevailing thought of his day, that the original substance of matter must be an eternal, unlimited reservoir of qualities and change.
Early Life
Anaximander (uh-nak-suh-MAN-duhr) was a fellow citizen and student of Thales, the Milesian usually credited with having inaugurated Western philosophy. Thales, some forty years older than his protégé, put none of his philosophical thought in writing and maintained no formal pedagogical associations with pupils. However, Thales’ cosmological views (as reconstructed by historians) doubtless inspired Anaximander, and Anaximander finally expanded on Thales’ ideas with innovative leaps in conceptual abstraction.
![Anaximander, detail view from "The School of Athen", Raphael Santi, 1510/11, cutting of the Vatican, Rome. See page for author [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons 88258650-77542.jpg](https://imageserver.ebscohost.com/img/embimages/ers/sp/embedded/88258650-77542.jpg?ephost1=dGJyMNHX8kSepq84xNvgOLCmsE2epq5Srqa4SK6WxWXS)
Anaximander was known in his day for his practical achievements and his astronomical discoveries. He is said to have been chosen by the Milesians as the leader for a new colony in Apollonia on the Black Sea. He traveled widely and was the first Greek to publish a “geographical tablet,” a map of the world. The map was circular, and it was centered on the city of Delphi, because Delphi was the location of the omphalos, or “navel” stone, that was thought to be the center of Earth. Anaximander is also said to have designed a celestial map and to have specified the proportions of stellar orbits. In addition to the celestial map, he built a spherical model of the stars and planets, with Earth located at the center and represented as a disk or cylinder whose height was one third its diameter. The heavenly bodies were rings of hollow pipe of different sizes that were placed on circling wheels in ratios of three to six to nine, in proportion to the magnitude of Earth. This model was dynamic; the wheels could be moved at different speeds, making it possible to visualize patterns of planetary motion. Anaximander is also credited with inventing the gnomon (part of a sundial) and with having discovered the zodiac.
All these eclectic interests and discoveries illustrate, with elegance, Anaximander’s particular genius, namely, his rational view of the world. This way of thinking was quite an innovation at a time when both scientific and protophilosophical thought took their content from the mythical and literary traditions, and thus were marked by vagueness and mystery. Anaximander viewed the world as steadily legible; he had the expectation of its rational intelligibility. His map of the world and his model of the heavens show his anticipation of symmetry and order. Earth, he argued, remained at rest in the center of the cosmos by reason of its equidistance at all points to the celestial circumference; it had no reason to be pulled in one direction in preference to any other. He projected the celestial orbits in perfect and pleasing proportions, and he anticipated regular motions.
Anaximander’s mapping and modeling techniques themselves were products of his rationalistic thinking. Models and maps relocate some set of unified phenomena into a new level of abstraction. Implicit in map and model design is the assumption that the abstractions will preserve the intelligible relationships present in the world that they reproduce. Thus Anaximander’s introduction of models and maps represents a tremendous and utterly original conceptual leap from the world “seen” to the world’s operations understood and faithfully reproduced by the abstracting human mind.
Life’s Work
Anaximander’s rational view of the world received its fullest and most innovative expression in his philosophy of nature. Here one finds the first unified and all-encompassing picture of the world of human experience in history that is based on rational deduction and explanation of all phenomena.
In order to understand Anaximander properly, his terminology must be put into its historical context. What Anaximander (and Thales as well) understood by “nature” is not quite the same as its modern sense. In Ionian Greece, physis denoted the process of growth and emergence. It also denoted something’s origin, or source, that from which the thing is constantly renewed. Nature, in the Ionian sense of physis, had nothing to do with matter; even Aristotle was mistaken in thinking that it did. In fact, no word for matter even existed in Anaximander’s day. It is also important to note that Anaximander’s thought is reconstructed entirely from ancient secondary sources. The one extant fragment of Anaximander’s own words is the quotation of an ancient historian. Thus, any explication of Anaximander’s thought is, to some extent, conjectural and interpretive.
Anaximander’s philosophy of nature arose in part as a response to Thales’ ideas on nature. Thales held that water was the nature of everything. This meant, in the light of the ancient idea of physis, that water was the origin of everything, that everything was sustained by, and constantly renewed from, water. This notion does not have any allegorical or mythical connotations in Thales’ formulation. Water is the ordinary physical stuff in the world, not some engendering god such as the Oceanus of Thales’ predecessors. That is the reason Thales is the first philosopher: He had a theory about the origin of things that competed with ancient creation myths.
Anaximander agreed with Thales that the origin of the things of the world was some common stuff, but he thought that the stuff could not be some ordinary element. He rejected Thales’ conception on purely logical grounds, and his reasoning was quite interesting. How could any manifestly singular stuff ever give rise to qualities that pertained to things differently constituted, such as earth and fire? What is more, if water were the source of things, would not drying destroy them? Thus, reasoned Anaximander, the thing with which the world begins cannot be identical with any of the ordinary stuff with which humans are acquainted, but it must be capable of giving rise to the wide multiplicity of things and their pairs of contrary qualities. What therefore distinguishes the source from the world is that the source itself is “unbounded”: It can have no definite shape or quality of its own but must be a reservoir from which every sort or characteristic in the world may be spawned. So Anaximander called the source of things this very name: apeiron, Boundlessness, or the Boundless. Anaximander designated the Boundless an arche, a beginning, but he did not mean a temporal beginning. The Boundless can have no beginning, nor can it pass away, for it can have no bounds, including temporal ones.
Thus the eternal source, the Boundless, functions as a storehouse of the world’s qualities, such that the qualities that constitute some present state of the world have been separated out of the stock, and when their contrary qualities become manifest, they will, in turn, be reabsorbed into the reservoir. When Earth is hot, heat will come forth from the Boundless; when Earth cools, cold will come forth and heat will go back. For Anaximander, this process continued in never-ending cycles.
The cause of the alternating manifestations of contrary qualities is the subject of the single existing fragment of Anaximander’s own words, the only remains of the first philosophy ever written. Out of the Boundless, Anaximander explains, the worlds arise, but
from whatever things is the genesis of the things that are, into these they must pass away according to necessity; for they must pay the penalty and make atonement to one another for their injustice according to the ordering of Time.
History has produced no consensus of interpretation for this passage and its picturesque philosophical metaphor for the rationale of the world. Anaximander was probably thinking of a courtroom image. Each existing thing is in a state of “having-too-much,” so that during the time it exists it “commits injustice” against its opposite by preventing it from existing. In retribution, the existing thing must cede its overt existence for its opposite to enjoy and pay the penalty of returning to the submerged place in the great Boundless reservoir. This cycling, he added, is how Time is ordered or measured. Time is the change, the alternating manifestation of opposites.
Here is the apotheosis of Anaximander’s rational worldview. The world’s workings are not simply visible and perspicuous, but neither are they whimsical and mysterious. The hidden workings of things may be revealed in the abstractions of the human mind. The world works, and is the way that it is, according to an eternal and intelligible principle. What is more, this world and its workings are unified, indeed form a cosmos. The cosmos, in turn, can be understood and explained by analogy with the human world; the justice sought in the city’s courts is the same justice that sustains everything that human perception finds in the universe.
Significance
Classical antiquity credited Thales with having pioneered philosophy. Anaximander, with his scientific curiosity and his genius for abstract insight, poised philosophical inquiry for new vistas of exploration; his new philosophical approach inaugurated penetrating, objective analysis. His principle of the eternal Boundless as the source of the world’s multifarious qualities and change forms the conceptual backdrop against which twenty-five centuries of science and natural philosophy have developed.
Two particular innovations of Anaximander have never been abandoned. First, his extension of the concept of law from human society to the physical world continues to dictate the scientific worldview. The received view in Anaximander’s time—that nature was capricious and anarchic—has never again taken hold. Second, Anaximander’s invention of the use of models and maps revolutionized science and navigation and continues to be indispensable, even in people’s daily lives. All scientific experiments are models of a sort: They are laboratory-scale contrivances of events or circumstances in the world at large. Purely visual three-dimensional models continue to be crucial in scientific discoveries: the so-called Bohr model of the atom played a crucial role in physics; the double-helical model was important to the discovery of the structure and function of deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA). Maps are taken for granted now, but if human beings had relied on verbal descriptions of spatial localities, civilization would not have proceeded very far.
Thus, Anaximander’s innovations and influence persist. Indeed, it is difficult to imagine a world without his contributions. Anaximander himself could hardly have seen all the implications of his discoveries, for even now one can only guess at the future direction of abstract thought.
Bibliography
Brumbaugh, Robert S. The Philosophers of Greece. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1981. This volume contains a short, digested chapter on Anaximander’s life and accomplishments. Emphasizes cartography and engineering. Includes a reproduction of the first map designed by Anaximander.
Burnet, John. Early Greek Philosophy. 4th ed. New York: Meridian Books/World, 1961. A detailed scholarly analysis of Anaximander’s thought in the context of comparisons with, and influences on, other pre-Socratic philosophers.
Couprie, Dirk L., Robert Hahn, and Gerard Naddaf. Anaximander in Context: New Studies in the Origins of Greek Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2002. Examines the social, political, cosmological, astronomical, and technological backgrounds in which Anaximander’s thought developed.
Guthrie, W. K. C. The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans. Vol. 1 in A History of Greek Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978-1990. Contains a chapter on Anaximander’s cosmology. Focuses in a very close analysis on the concepts of apeiron and apeiron as arche.
Hahn, Robert. Anaximander and the Architects: The Contributions of Egyptian and Greek Architectural Technologies to the Origins of Greek Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2001. Posits that technologies emerging among Egyptian and Greek architects strongly impacted the development of Greek philosophy.
Kahn, Charles H. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994. Surveys the documentary evidence for Anaximander’s views, reconstructs a detailed cosmology from documentary texts, and devotes an entire chapter to analysis and interpretation of Anaximander’s fragment.
Kirk, Geoffrey S., and John E. Raven. The Presocratic Philosophers. 2d ed. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1983. Contains a chapter on Anaximander and a close formal analysis of textual testimony on Anaximander’s thought.
Wheelwright, Philip, ed. The Presocratics. New York: Odyssey Press, 1966. A primary source. Contains the Anaximander fragment in translation. Also contains testimonies from Aristotle and other Greek and Latin sources who read and commented on Anaximander’s treatise.