Isocrates
Isocrates was an influential ancient Greek rhetorician and educator, born in 436 BCE in Athens. He hailed from a wealthy family, which allowed him to receive an exceptional education, studying under prominent figures such as Protagoras and Gorgias. Despite his aspirations for a political career, Isocrates struggled with stage fright and a weak voice, leading him to focus on rhetoric and education instead. He established the first permanent institution of liberal arts education in Athens around 392 BCE, where he taught the art of rhetoric and emphasized the importance of oratory in civic life.
Isocrates' teachings significantly shaped the future of rhetorical practice, influencing notable figures like Cicero and Demosthenes. He believed that rhetoric was not only a tool for persuasion but also a means of acquiring knowledge and moral reasoning. His writings often addressed cultural issues and promoted a vision of a united Greece, urging students to take pride in their education and civic responsibilities. Isocrates emphasized the development of effective communication skills as essential for informed citizenship and civic engagement, making his legacy relevant in both historical and educational contexts. He died in 338 BCE, leaving behind a profound impact on rhetoric and education that lasted for centuries.
On this Page
Subject Terms
Isocrates
Greek philosopher
- Born: 436 b.c.e.
- Birthplace: Athens, Greece
- Died: 338 b.c.e.
- Place of death: Athens, Greece
One of the ten Attic Orators, Isocrates made significant contributions to the development of rhetorical theory, philosophy, and education in ancient Greece. Isocrates’ model of education, grounded in rhetoric, guided educators for centuries to follow.
Early Life
Isocrates (i-SAWK-ruh-teez) was born during the archonship of Lysimachus in 436 b.c.e. His father, Theodorus, was a wealthy flute maker. His father’s wealth afforded Isocrates the finest education of the day. He studied under such luminaries as Protagoras, Prodicus, Gorgias, Theramenes, and Tisias and joined the circle of Socrates. In Phaedros (388-368 b.c.e.; Phaedrus, 1792), Plato described Isocrates as a “youth of great promise.”
![Bust of Isocrates. From page 155 of the World's Famous Orations Vol 1. Cropped. By William Jennings Bryan. Francis Whiting Halsey [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons 88258774-77603.jpg](https://imageserver.ebscohost.com/img/embimages/ers/sp/embedded/88258774-77603.jpg?ephost1=dGJyMNHX8kSepq84xNvgOLCmsE2epq5Srqa4SK6WxWXS)
Isocrates desperately wanted to play an important role in Athenian politics. A powerful case of stage fright coupled with a weak voice precluded his participation in the public-oratory-driven Athenian Assembly. In 404, during the reign of the “Thirty Tyrants,” Isocrates fled to the island of Chios, where he operated a small school of rhetoric. As a result of the Peloponnesian War, Isocrates’ father, Theodorus, lost most of his property and wealth. Thus, in 403 Isocrates returned to Athens, where, as a result of financial need, he became a “forensic locographer,” writing speeches for others to deliver in the courts. After only six speeches, Isocrates discovered that he lacked the practical gifts for winning cases and abandoned the profession. Isocrates would later disavow his career as a locographer, scorning the profession.
In 392, at the age of forty-four, Isocrates set himself up as a teacher of rhetoric. His academy, located near the Lyceum in Athens, became the first permanent institution of liberal arts education, preceding Plato’s Academy by five years. Isocrates announced the school and his new profession while attacking his sophistic competition with his essay Kata tōn sophistfū (c. 394 b.c.e.; Against the Sophists, 1929)
Life’s Work
Isocrates’ main legacy is the impact of his teachings on future generations of oratory and education. Isocrates’ Academy was the most successful of all the Grecian schools of rhetoric. Cicero holds that this was the school in which all the eloquence of Greece was perfected, and alumni of Isocrates’ academy are among the greatest statesmen, historians, writers, and orators of their time. There is evidence that even Aristotle may have been a pupil of Isocrates. Cicero and Demosthenes used Isocrates’ work as a model, and through their work, Isocrates shaped generations of rhetorical thought and practice. Isocrates’ style was incorporated into the works of orators, writers, and historians and was passed down for more than nine centuries.
Isocrates would admit only those students who had mastered grammar and could demonstrate previous knowledge in mathematics and the sciences. He believed that this knowledge was necessary grounding for the mental gymnastics of rhetoric, philosophy, and civics. Isocrates also demanded that potential students must demonstrate promise in voice control, intellect, and confidence. He believed that there were three essential qualities necessary for learning: natural ability, training, and experience. The training included studies in composition, debate, literature, philosophy, math, and history. Isocrates was also the first educator to utilize imitation and models as educational tools. The Panegyricus (c. 380 b.c.e.; English translation, 1928) and the Plataicus (c. 373 b.c.e.; English translation, 1945) were written as model speeches for his pupils.
Isocrates’ students were always expected to write and speak about cultural issues, with particular attention to the keeping of a panhellenic Greece above all nations. While style and diction were important, for the first time content was stressed in an academic setting. This content served to train the student in Isocrates’ Hellenic ideology. The model orations that his students studied were propagandistic in that they professed Isocrates’ political beliefs. Isocrates taught, and wrote in Panegyricus, that “Greek” denoted a man’s education, not his race. Isocrates was sorely troubled by the petty squabbles that kept the various city-states at odds. He longed for a Greece that could stand united, and he planted this desire in his students.
In the light of Isocrates’ patriotism, it is unremarkable that the primary focus of his educational plan was the development of citizen-orators. He considered political science and rhetoric nearly one and the same. Greek society was driven by oratory, and Isocrates taught that those who are the best users of speech are those of greatest wisdom. He held that all the great works of humankind are the result of rhetoric. As he wrote in Antidosis (c. 354 b.c.e.; English translation, 1929), “There is no institution devised by man which the power of speech has not helped to establish.” Isocrates taught that proper speaking was a sign of proper thinking and that the properly educated citizen was conspicuous for his eloquence.
Although Isocrates’ known works contain no definition of rhetoric, he did describe the functions of rhetoric: “With this faculty we both contend against others on matters which are open to dispute and seek light for ourselves on things which are unknown.” For Isocrates, rhetoric was an epistemic, or knowledge-discovering, tool that guides thought and action and that demonstrates wisdom. In Against the Sophists, he taught that good oratory is speech that proves appropriate for an occasion while demonstrating proper style and originality. In Panegyricus, he added that timeliness was also a key to good oratory.
Another function of good oratory, for Isocrates, is eloquence, and he freed Greek prose from the stiff style of earlier periods. He created and mastered a smoothly rolling style of prose and elevated oratory to a formal art. His style involved precise vocabulary, few figures of speech, and many illustrations from history and philosophy. He believed that good oratory was very polished, as demonstrated by his taking ten years to refine Panegyricus for release.
Isocrates also professed that rhetoric is philosophic in that it teaches morals and politics. By “philosophy,” Isocrates was describing a theory of culture. He believed that “philosophy” was the study of how to be a reasonable and useful citizen. Isocrates held that one should deliberate about both one’s own affairs and the affairs of the state. He believed that a philosophic education should arouse intense patriotism as well as construct a personal philosophy close to the stoic ideal.
While Isocrates did not believe that virtue could be taught, he argued in Against the Sophists that it could be strengthened through training and practice in oratory. He argued that moral argumentation encourages right action because argumentation produces a historical narrative that uses historic events as precedents for present action. Therefore, one gains moral knowledge by studying public address as the art of oratory and by imitating the great speakers. As he wrote in Antidosis, the lessons made “by a man’s life” are stronger than lessons furnished by words.
Isocrates also saw the relationship between morality and oratory as reciprocal. In Antidosis, Isocrates explained that the more one wishes to persuade one’s fellow citizens, the more important it is that the orator have a favorable reputation among those citizens. This notion served as the basis for the Roman rhetorician Quintilian’s definition of ethos, or credibility, as a good man speaking well.
The concept that rhetorical training is moral training is hinged on Isocrates’ notion that the test of all virtue or truth lies in that which wins approval. For Isocrates, it is through rhetoric that one can approximate truth, or at least a consensual truth. One who is trained in rhetoric is trained in truth, and in the creation of that truth through oratory. In Antidosis, he writes that “thanks to speech, we educate the fools and put the wise to the test; for we consider the fact of speaking rightly as the greatest sign of correct thinking.” Thus, for Isocrates, there is no absolute truth, only consensual truth created by rhetoric.
Isocrates also believed that rhetoric had a role to play in the study of history. He made the study of history an art, not a science as Aristotle would have it. Isocrates began the tendency for a writer or speaker to idolize the past and use examples of the past to guide political attitudes and actions in the present. He also promoted the practice of glorifying individual figures, heroes, as catalysts of history. The outstanding historians of the fourth century, Ephorus of Cumae and Theopompus of Chios, were both pupils of Isocrates, and they introduced Isocrates’ rhetorical style into the construction of history. There is also evidence that Xenophon, the greatest of fourth century historians, was intellectually influenced by Isocrates’ Evagoras (c. 365 b.c.e.; English translation, 1945). From Isocrates forward, history has been more than an objective recounting of events; history has been patriotic.
Ironically, the man that Cicero termed “the master of all rhetoricians” did not himself speak in public. In Philippos (c. 344 b.c.e.; To Philip, 1928), Isocrates explained that “nature has placed me more at a disadvantage than any of my fellow-citizens for a public career: I was not given a strong enough voice nor sufficient assurance to deal with the mob, to take abuse, and bandy words with the men who haunt the rostrum.” As a result, his writings were meant to be read and are considered to be the earliest political pamphlets known. Through these oratorical pamphlets, Isocrates espoused a brand of Hellenism that would unite all Greeks together against a common foe. In his later years, Isocrates urged Philip II, king of Macedonia, to unite the Greeks under his leadership in a war against Persia.
Relatively late in his life, Isocrates married the daughter of Hippias, a Sophist. He died in the Archonship of Chaerondas in 338, reportedly starving himself to death at the age of ninety-eight after hearing the news of Philip’s victory over Athens in the Battle of Chaeronea.
Significance
Isocrates was the first of a series of great teachers who equated rhetoric and education. His method of teaching students to speak well on noble subjects, vir bonus dicendi peritus, remained the ideal of the ancient world. The creation of this ideal kept the rhetorical practices of the Greeks alive and passed that knowledge on to the Romans. Isocrates’ significance rests, then, on the influence he had on those who followed him. His ideas were carried on through such luminaries as the Athenian general Timotheus; Nicocles, the ruler of Salamis, in Cyprus; the Roman rhetoricians Cicero and Quintilian; and the historians Ephorus, Theopompus, and Xenophon. Against the Sophists served as the prototype for Plato’s Gorgias (399-390 b.c.e.; English translation, 1804), and Isocrates’ name is mentioned more than that of any other rhetorician in Aristotle’s Technē rhetorikēs (335-323 b.c.e.; Rhetoric, 1686).
The tradition of Isocrates runs silently through intellectual history, in that the art of the rhetorician is manifest in all human practices that are dependent on effective communication. The tradition of vir bonus dicendi peritus continues in all scholarship in the attempt to create consensual truth. Moreover Isocrates’ refinement of the Greek ideal of educating the individual for an active life in the service of the state widened the bounds of education. Cicero reported Isocrates’ style of teaching oratory through his writings, and it became the standard of excellence for rhetorical education in Europe until the Renaissance. Components of this broad-based “liberal arts” education remain in the curricula of many modern schools.
Bibliography
Benoit, William L. “Isocrates on Rhetorical Education.” Communication Education 33 (1984): 109-119. Provides a thorough analysis of Isocratean rhetorical study. Examines the whole of Isocrates’ body of works and the impact that these works have had through the centuries.
Bury, J. B. A History of Greece. 4th ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1991. The standard history of Greece, providing a detailed account of Greek history from the dawn of Western civilization to the death of Alexander the Great.
Golden, James L., Goodwin F. Berquist, and William E. Coleman. The Rhetoric of Western Thought. 7th ed. Dubuque, Iowa: Kendall/Hunt, 2000. A thorough history of the development of rhetorical theory and practice; contains a chapter on Isocrates, Cicero, and Quintilian. The standard work in the field of rhetorical theory.
Grube, G. M. A. The Greek and Roman Critics. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1968. Complete coverage of the Greek and Roman philosophers, from Homer and Hesiod through Longinus. Delineates connections between individual thinkers and schools of thought. Clearly shows Isocrates’ role in the broadening of rhetorical theory.
Poulakos, Takis. Speaking for the Polis: Isocrates’ Rhetorical Education. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 1997. This study in rhetoric and communication includes bibliography and index.
Romilly, Jacqueline de. Magic and Rhetoric in Ancient Greece. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1975. An unusual, enlightening treatment of the intellectual development of logos (rhetoric) and magic. Includes a section on the works of Isocrates.