Beyond Good and Evil by Friedrich Nietzsche
"Beyond Good and Evil" is a seminal philosophical work by Friedrich Nietzsche, published in 1886, that challenges traditional notions of morality and truth. Written during Nietzsche's intellectual maturity, the text explores the origins and implications of moral values, arguing that they often reflect deeper psychological and physiological drives rather than objective realities. Nietzsche critiques established philosophers, such as Kant and Hegel, for their dualistic approaches and instead advocates for a more nuanced, experimental method of philosophical inquiry.
Central to the work is the idea of the "will to power," which Nietzsche posits as a fundamental driving force in human beings, surpassing the mere instinct for self-preservation. He encourages readers to question the prevailing moral frameworks influenced by Christianity and to recognize that values are not absolute but must evolve over time. Nietzsche's approach emphasizes the importance of life-affirming values that promote creativity and individuality, suggesting that the future philosopher should be one who commands rather than merely describes. This provocative text continues to resonate across disciplines, inviting readers to reevaluate their own beliefs about morality, truth, and existence.
Beyond Good and Evil by Friedrich Nietzsche
First published:Jenseits von Gut und Böse: Vorspiel einer Philosophie der Zukunft, 1886 (English translation, 1907)
Type of Philosophy: Ethics, philosophy of religion
Context
Friedrich Nietzsche holds a commanding historical significance in modern thought in spite of a continuing controversy about his stature as a philosophical mind. Many scholars refuse to judge Nietzsche’s brilliant writings as serious philosophical contributions. They prefer to view him as a poet, as a critic of culture and religion, or even as a superb master of the German language. Yet some scholars insist on Nietzsche’s importance as a genuine philosophical figure—a lonely, disturbed thinker who anticipated criticism of the classical ideal of a rigorously deductive model of philosophical knowledge and of the accompanying belief in the possibility of a completed metaphysics. Nietzsche felt keenly the impact of Darwinian evolutionary views that so stirred many nineteenth century thinkers in a number of intellectual fields. As a philosopher, he must be included in that group of thinkers for whom the philosopher’s primary function is to lay bare the unexamined assumptions and buried cultural influences lurking behind supposedly disinterested moral and metaphysical constructions.
![Title page, first edition, Beyond Good and Evil, by Friedrich Nietzsche By C. G. Naumann, publisher [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons 89876392-62210.jpg](https://imageserver.ebscohost.com/img/embimages/ers/sp/embedded/89876392-62210.jpg?ephost1=dGJyMNHX8kSepq84xNvgOLCmsE2epq5Srqa4SK6WxWXS)
Symptomatically, Beyond Good and Evil begins with a chapter entitled “About Philosophers’ Prejudices.” Written during Nietzsche’s intellectual maturity, hard on the heels of a lengthy literary development yet prior to the illness that ended his career, this book reflects the many important central tendencies of his thought. Its contents illustrate the surprisingly wide range of Nietzsche’s intellectual interests: the origin and nature of moral valuations, the history and psychology of religion, the psychology of human motivation, and historical processes. Nietzsche often uses aphorisms that, though unsystematic from a logical point of view, manage to express a tolerably consistent philosophical viewpoint.
Nietzsche’s writings contain numerous passages that suggest similar positions worked out in greater psychotherapeutic detail by Sigmund Freud. Frequently, he shows greater interest in the question, “What are the motives of philosophizing?” than in “What do philosophers say?” When he turns to an analysis of moral judgments, Nietzsche worries about what may hide submerged in such valuations—much as a student of icebergs wants to discover what exists beneath the surface. Perhaps the valuations produced by moralists always represent a perspective on things in the sense that there may exist no final metaphysical standpoint from which to render such valuations.
In a similar manner, the philosophical quest after truth may peculiarly express what Nietzsche terms the “will to power” rather than a disinterested description of things. Even assuming that genuine truth can be obtained in principle, Nietzsche points out that the value of an idea has greater significance than the truth of the idea. The value perspectives by which individuals live may be necessary and yet not objective. “Un-truth” may carry greater value than “truth” in many situations. Such perspectives must be judged in terms of the degree to which they are life-furthering. Early in Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche suggests, “Even behind logic and its apparent sovereignty of development stand value judgments, or, to speak more plainly, physiological demands for preserving a certain type of life.” On this supposition, a psychologist would ask of any belief whether it is conducive to sound health (a therapeutic matter) rather than whether it is true. “True” and “health-producing” become synonymous in Nietzsche’s treatment of ideas.
Physiology and Philosophy
Nietzsche criticizes a philosopher such as Immanuel Kant for having assumed existence of an unknowable “thing-in-itself” behind the phenomenal universe available to science. Similarly, he shows scorn for Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, who sought to find in the antithetical aspects of existence (passions, ideas, moral valuations) the expressions of a more fundamental rational reality. The tendency toward dualism, by which the “I” as subject stands independent of that which is perceived (as well as logically distinct as “subject” against “object”), receives criticism as a possible grammatical prejudice erected into a false and misleading metaphysical argument. Rather than philosophizing in “the grand manner,” Nietzsche encourages piecemeal treatment of a host of specific, clearly stated problems. Physiology may hold the key to the solution of a number of old and baffling questions, including moral ones.
Philosophical investigators must forgo easy solutions happening to fit their prejudices—just as physiologists must cease thinking that the basic drive behind organic life is that toward self-preservation. The will to power may prove more fundamental than desire of self-preservation. The will to power expresses an expansive, assimilating, positive, value-creating tendency in existence, nonhuman as well as human. There may also be no immediate certainties like the philosopher’s “I think” or “Schopenhauer’s superstition, I will.’” The older superstition that thinking activity results from a human will requires sophisticated and subtle analysis, for “A thought comes when it’ and not when I’ will.” Indeed, even to say “It is thought” instead of “I think” may cause another set of misleading metaphysical puzzles to arise. Nietzsche also argues that the metaphysical question about freedom of the will results from misuses of terms such as “cause” and “effect,” which are simply concepts. These concepts are fictions useful for the facilitation of common understanding but not as explanations. People must stop creating myths about an objective reality based on pure concepts useful for other ends. There is neither “free” nor “nonfree” will, according to Nietzsche, but simply “strong will and weak will.”
Psychological investigations done prior to Nietzsche’s day are found suspect because of the subtle ways in which their conclusions reflect human prejudices and fears. This theme sounds constantly throughout Nietzsche’s writings. Nietzsche wanted a new kind of psychologist able to resist the unconscious forces influencing one to accept conclusions dictated by one’s “heart.” The evidence is what must count in such investigations. He asks his readers to imagine an investigator in physiology-psychology who possesses the courage to believe that greed, hatred, envy, and such passions are “the passions on which life is conditioned, as things that must be present in the total household of life.” So, too, the new philosophical breed will approach the study of the origins of morals with a ruthless honesty.
Values
In a later book, Zur Genealogie der Moral (1887; On the Genealogy of Morals, 1896), Nietzsche in practice attempted the kind of historical-genetic investigation his Beyond Good and Evil recommends in principle. In the former book, it is suggested that the concepts “good” and “bad,” as well as “good” and “evil,” arose out of a spiteful transvaluation of classical values by the meek and the lowly. “Evil” is the valuation placed on acts previously termed “good” in an aristocratic, healthy culture. Jewish and Christian priests, expressing their hatred of life, described as “evil” those biological functions fundamental to creation and healthful strength.
The central suggestion in Beyond Good and Evil is that another transvaluation of human values must now follow from the evolutionary notion of the will to power—that the cultural standpoint of Western Europe so influenced by Christian valuations must undergo a deep change to usher in gigantic, even sometimes cataclysmic, alterations in the table of values. Humanity must “get beyond” existing valuations in order to live creatively and even dangerously. A culture whose established values are foundering, in which the faith in metaphysical absolutes wobbles unsteadily on aging legs, throws up the question whether the belief in the possibility of an objectively justifiable morality is an illusion. Never does Nietzsche say that people can live without making valuations. Nor does he argue that moral valuations are unqualifiedly relative—one as good as another. His point is psychological and critical. Nietzsche believed that human nature, a product of evolution, demands the constant creation of new valuations even in the face of the absence of absolute standards. This aspect of his thought brings to mind existentialist thought that, however differently expressed by numerous existentialist writers, responds to the anguish of the human situation by making value judgments possible even though absolutes are lacking.
Nietzsche warns that the new philosopher must guard against some of the characteristics of the “intellectuals.” Nietzsche cautions against bringing up a German generation so preoccupied with history that the value of those things whose history is studied could receive neither affirmation nor denial. Intellectualistic pursuit of objective knowledge tends to weaken the critical and evaluative capacities needed as a basis for living. Nietzsche never ridicules the scientific quest after objective knowledge as such. What he warns against is the production of scientific minds unable to make judgments about better and worse. Objective knowledge functions valuably only as a means to some other end or ends, such as those that actualize human potentiality in all its possible varieties. Scientific knowledge fails to show people what they should agree to or object to from a valuational standpoint. Judgment is a function of the will—something that the scientific person can never determine.
For many centuries, people decided on the value of actions by reference to their consequences. Nietzsche calls this the premoral period. Because he elsewhere caricatures English utilitarian thought, one must assume that Nietzsche thinks little of a value standard based on the tendency of acts to produce pleasure rather than pain. A second period, lasting for the past ten thousand years (according to Nietzsche, who made no anthropological survey of such an enormous space of historical time), is marked by a predominant tendency to judge the value or worthlessness of an act by its origins. “The origin of an action was interpreted to rest, in a very definite sense, on an intent.” Such an intentional yardstick for judging actions reflected an aristocratic stance. In his own time, Nietzsche believed neither the intent nor the consequences of an act would play the crucial role. This would be the amoral period. In a famous passage, Nietzsche characterizes the nature of the philosophers who would conduct new amoral analyses of human valuations:
A new species of philosopher is coming up over the horizon. I risk baptizing them with a name that is not devoid of peril. As I read them (as they allow themselves to be read—for it is characteristic of their type that they wish to remain riddles in some sense), these philosophers of the future have a right (perhaps also a wrong!) to be called: Experimenters. This name itself is only an experiment, and, if you will, a temptation.
These thinkers will view pain and suffering as the necessary preconditions of any new valuations. They will also issue commands rather than simply describe or explain.
Religion
Nietzsche’s treatment of what he calls “the peculiar nature of religion” bears a crucial relation to his prophesied transvaluation of existing values. According to Nietzsche, students of religious phenomena should develop that kind of malicious subtlety that moral investigators need in all times and places if they are to succeed in their work. Although he despised the moral values taught by traditional Christianity, Nietzsche nonetheless admired the psychological self-discipline of the Christian saints. Religious phenomena fascinated him. The faith demanded of early Christians, a rarely attained reality, provides an example possessing peculiarly tough and lasting appeal. Nietzsche writes that contemporary people lack the corresponding toughness to appreciate the paradoxical statement of faith: God died on a cross.
Early Christian faith demanded qualities found in the philosopher Blaise Pascal, according to Nietzsche. In Pascal, this faith “looks in a horrible way like a continuous suicide of the reason, a tough, long-lived, worm-like reason that cannot be killed at one time and with one blow.” Nietzsche believed that such a faith would require careful study if the new experimenters were to learn how to succeed in their own transvaluation of Christian values. Especially intriguing are the three restrictions associated with what Nietzsche calls “the religious neurosis”: solitude, fasting, and sexual abstinence. For students to understand the earlier historical transvaluation that occurred, they must answer the question, “How is the saint possible?” Genuinely to understand how from the “bad” person one gets, suddenly, a saint, requires one to compare Christianity’s valuations to the lavish gratitude characteristic of earlier Greek religion before fear made Christianity a possibility.
Moral Analysis
Nietzsche argues that the study of moral and religious phenomena can never be the work of a day or a brief season. Modern thinkers can hope only to assemble the necessary evidence, slowly and painstakingly. Their first concern is the statement of a morphology of morality rather than the former ambitious attempt to give a philosophical justification of the derivation of a morality. Only “the collection of the material, the conceptual formalization and arrangement of an enormous field of delicate value-feelings and value-differences that are living, growing, generating others, and perishing” is possible at the present time along with some observations about recurrent features of these value growths. Investigators must know where to look for the proper evidence. For this task, the scientific person lacks the capacities needed for directing the investigations. The scientific person functions best as an instrument—an enormously valuable one. Yet the instrument “belongs in the hands of one who has greater power”—one who commands what uses the instrument shall be put to. Most philosophers also fail to qualify for this kind of moral analysis. The reason is that they have reduced philosophizing to theory of knowledge, which produces a value skepticism when what is required is action—value commanding and value judging.
The whole problem of understanding moral valuations is reminiscent of the older faith-versus-reason controversy in theology. Does “instinct” (the tendency to act creatively without always knowing how to give reasons for one’s actions) hold a more important place in the subject matter of moral analysis than reasoning (the capacity to give reasons for one’s valuations)? This problem emerges early in the character of Socrates—a philosopher whom Nietzsche admires for his magnificent irony and dialectical skills even though Nietzsche denounces “Socratism,” the dogma that beliefs are valuable only insofar as they are capable of logical justification. Nietzsche considers Socrates a much greater figure than Plato. Socrates knew how to laugh at himself, realizing that his superior powers failed to discover the means by which to justify many beliefs he held important. Plato was more naïve than Socrates. Plato left a moral prejudice that Nietzsche simply rejects: the view that instinct and reason ultimately seek the same end—”God” or “the Good.” Plato, in thus dissolving all that Nietzsche finds fascinating in the faith-reason controversy, made possible a later Christian institutionalization of herd-morality.
Fundamentally, Nietzsche distrusts individuals who venerate reason and deny the value of instinct. He insists that people of action illustrate the gap that exists between those who merely know (intellectually) and those who act. Any existing morality needs a horizon provided by people of action who say: “It shall be thus!” This command source of any morality must itself go unjustified and unquestioned. Any existing morality is in this sense always “problematic.” By this Nietzsche probably meant that after reasons for the existing valuations have been given, there must remain, at last, a self-justifying command for which no further reasons are possible. Indeed, all morality containing progressive aspects stems from an aristocratic type of commanding. Every command requires a commander, some individual who supplies the necessary value horizon that others must simply accept. There can be no objectively grounded perspective of all perspectives. Life as an expanding process requires the cutting off of deliberative procedures at some point.
Nietzsche was willing to accept some of the painful consequences of this view of the command origin of all moral valuations. One consequence is that any existing morality requires sacrifice of numerous individuals and of many nuances of feeling and human tendency. Morality requires the application of command in such a way that not all legitimately natural instincts can find total expression at any one time. It also rests on exploitation as a necessary element in the creation of values. Some instincts must give way to others—and the commanding ones ought to be domineering and aristocratic. There must occur “the forcing of one’s own forms upon something else.”
Nietzsche’s analysis of morality led him to dislike equalitarian democracy and herd-utilitarianism (“the greatest happiness of the greatest number”). An order of rank must exist. Between commander and commanded must arise a social distance based on the former’s greater value. The new philosopher seeking to transform valuations must stand “against his own time”—finding a value standpoint “beyond” the accepted valuations of his own era. To do so requires hardness and patient waiting. Philosophical success is thus partly a result of circumstances beyond any individual philosopher’s control. What his creative response shall be is a function of what the situation is in which he finds himself. In this sense the philosopher must always be a lonely individual, “beyond” the good and evil of conventional morality. This loneliness will produce anguish.
In Also sprach Zarathustra: Ein Buch für Alle und Keinen (1883-1885; Thus Spake Zarathustra, 1896), Nietzsche describes the anguish that results from the discovery that no God is found beyond good and evil. Nor is there a higher, more ultimate Platonic harmony. The new philosopher must learn to embrace existence for its own sake. Nietzsche attempts to express the nature of this love of existence through a doctrine of “eternal recurrence.” The philosopher of existence must say “yes” to reality while knowing that “God is dead.” Any new values that arise in the evolutionary process do so as expressions of people’s self-commanding capacity. Error and pain inevitably and necessarily are aspects of existence. “That everything recurs, is the very nearest approach of a world of Becoming to a world of Being: the height of contemplation,” he wrote in the second volume of Der Wille zur Macht (1901; The Will to Power, 1910), which was published from remaining notes by Nietzsche’s sister. The new philosopher of “beyondness” needs this doctrine of eternal recurrence because the new philosopher must command new values in an existence that expresses the will to power rather than a rational scheme of things.
In Nietzsche’s style one finds a brilliance to match his intellectual daring—a wealth of suggestion, irony, maliciousness, a fine balancing of value antitheses, and playful criticism coupled with the most serious intention. Nietzsche was (as he says all people are) a philosopher who worked from an inner necessity to achieve self-understanding. Of philosophers he wrote: “But fundamentally, way down below’ in us, there is something unteachable, a bedrock of intellectual destiny, of predestined decision, of answers to predestined selected questions.”
Principal Ideas Advanced
•Ideas that preserve life and add to a person’s power are more important than ideas sanctioned by logicians and seekers after the absolute.
•The metaphysical interest in the freedom of the will should give way to an interest in the strength of the will.
•People must turn conventional values upside down in order to live creatively; the established values of society were invented by the weak to enable them to triumph over the strong.
•Scientific minds are weak when they fail to pass judgment; whoever denies the will denies the power of life.
•Progress in life is possible only if there are people of action who have the courage to trust will and instinct; new values arise that go beyond conventional good and evil when the will to power asserts itself.
Bibliography
Berkowitz, Peter. Nietzsche: The Ethics of an Immoralist. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995. Shows how Friedrich Nietzsche’s attacks on conventional and traditional morality entail a distinctive ethical outlook.
Chessick, Richard D. A Brief Introduction to the Genius of Nietzsche. Lanham, Md.: University Press of America, 1983. One section deals specifically with Beyond Good and Evil. A wonderful primer for understanding the concepts of nihilism and eternal recurrence.
Conway, Daniel W. Nietzsche and the Political. New York: Routledge, 1997. A thoughtful discussion of the political implications of Nietzsche’s philosophy.
Copleston, Frederick. A History of Philosophy: Modern Philosophy. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1965. Copleston provides a good overview of Nietzsche’s thought and situates him in his nineteenth century European context.
Hayman, Ronald. Nietzsche. New York: Routledge, 1999. An excellent biographical introduction to the thoughts of the philosopher, clearly presented and requiring no special background. Bibliography.
Hayman, Ronald. Nietzsche: A Critical Life. New York: Oxford University Press, 1980. A chronological account of Nietzsche’s life and work.
Heilke, Thomas. Nietzsche’s Tragic Regime: Culture, Aesthetics, and Political Education. De Kalb: Northern Illinois University Press, 1998. A fascinating treatment of the theme of political education in Nietzsche’s early work.
Higgins, Kathleen. Nietzsche’s Zarathustra. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1987. Clearly written and accessible, this book explores in depth the themes and issues raised in Nietzsche’s work Thus Spake Zarathustra.
Jones, W. T. A History of Western Philosophy: Kant to Wittgenstein and Sartre. New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1969. Provides a good introductory discussion of Nietzsche’s main themes.
Kaufman, Walter Arnold. Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. 4th rev. ed. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1974. Underscores the radical nature of Nietzsche’s philosophy, especially given the Christian focus of the European literary world of his time.
Klein, Wayne. Nietzsche and the Promise of Philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997. Discusses Nietzsche’s vision of what philosophy should and should not be and traces the implications of his analysis.
Krell, David Farrell. The Good European: Nietzsche’s Work Sites in Word and Image. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997. Analyzes Nietzsche’s philosophy in relation to the contexts and places in which he developed his distinctive vision.
Krell, David Farrell. Infectious Nietzsche. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996. Shows how Nietzsche’s influence has been challenging, ongoing, and significant in ways that will continue to make him a thinker of immense importance.
Magnus, Bernd. Nietzsche’s Existential Imperative. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1978. An interpretation of Nietzsche that focuses on his doctrine of eternal recurrence and takes Thus Spake Zarathustra as a principal source.
Magnus, Bernd, and Kathleen M. Higgins, eds. The Cambridge Companion to Nietzsche. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1996. Nietzsche scholars contribute insightful articles about diverse aspects of his influential philosophy.
Mencken, H. L. “Beyond Good and Evil.” In Friedrich Nietzsche. New Brunswick: Transaction, 1993. A sympathetic treatment of Nietzsche’s work. Probes Nietzsche’s attacks on conventional morality.
Nehamas, Alexander. Nietzsche: Life as Literature. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985. An instructive interpretation of Nietzsche’s philosophy and his view that philosophy has close links to narrative.
Porter, James I. The Inversion of Dionysus: An Essay on “The Birth of Tragedy”. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford, 2000. An insightful interpretation of Nietzsche’s Birth of Tragedy.
Solomon, Robert C., ed. Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays. Garden City, N.J.: Anchor Press, 1973. A valuable collection of essays by such greats as Thomas Mann, George Bernard Shaw, and Hermann Hesse. Discusses Nietzsche’s views on nihilism, moral change, and eternal recurrence.
Stack, George J. Nietzsche: Man, Knowledge and Will to Power. Durango, Colo.: Hollowbrook Publishing, 1994. A modern and critical analysis of the major tenets of Beyond Good and Evil. Easy to follow and elucidating. Extended bibliography, detailed index, and footnotes.
Waite, Geoff. Nietzsche’s Corpse: Aesthetics, Politics, Prophecy, or, the Spectacular Technoculture of Everyday Life. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 1996. An assessment of Nietzsche’s significance and impact on the development of culture, politics, and technology in the twentieth century and beyond.