On Nature by Anaximander
"On Nature" by Anaximander represents a foundational text in the development of natural philosophy and science, marking a significant departure from mythological explanations of the universe. Anaximander, a successor of Thales, introduced the concept of the Boundless (apeiron) as the primordial substance from which all things emerge, positing that it is neither one of the traditional elements nor characterized by specific qualities like heat or cold. This philosophical framework suggests a continuous process of creation rather than distinct acts of divine intervention, reflecting an early form of evolutionary thought.
Anaximander also articulated a cosmological model in which the earth is an unsupported drum shape, maintaining its position at the center of the universe due to its equal distance from all surrounding celestial bodies. His innovative approach included postulating unseen entities, such as hoops that govern the movement of heavenly bodies, showcasing an early understanding of scientific reasoning. Additionally, he presented a theory of evolution, suggesting that human beings and other animals emerged from marine environments, adapting over time to survive in changing conditions.
Recognized as a precursor to scientific rationalism, Anaximander's ideas laid the groundwork for future philosophical inquiry and scientific exploration. His work profoundly influenced subsequent thinkers, demonstrating a remarkable blend of natural observation and theoretical reasoning that surged ahead of his contemporaries.
On Nature by Anaximander
First transcribed: sixth century b.c.e. (The Anaximander Fragment, 1982; commonly known as On Nature)
Type of Philosophy: Metaphysics
Context
Thales of Miletus is traditionally credited with having been the first philosopher because he was the first to put forward a nonmythological account of the origin and nature of things. However, we know no more of his views than that he claimed that all things originated from water, and it is unlikely that he worked out this thesis in detail. It remained for his “pupil and successor” Anaximander to produce the first comprehensive natural philosophy, a system of astonishing acumen and sophistication.
![Relief representing Anaximander (Roma, Museo Nazionale Romano). Probably Roman copy of an earlier Greek original. This is the only existing image of Anaximander from the ancient world. By Unknown. old art. [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons 89876482-62269.jpg](https://imageserver.ebscohost.com/img/embimages/ers/sp/embedded/89876482-62269.jpg?ephost1=dGJyMNHX8kSepq84xNvgOLCmsE2epq5Srqa4SK6WxWXS)
Anaximander conceived his problem to be that of explaining how the present constitution of the universe developed out of a primordial condition of simplicity. Apparently he did not consider the possibility that things had always been much the same. To this extent, he inherited the notion of evolution from Near Eastern mythologies, which all told of how the world had been fashioned out of a preexisting “chaos” or homogeneous matter, usually water. However, in rejecting divine personal agency and in substituting a (more or less) continuous process for separate acts of creation, Anaximander radically transformed the idea.
The Boundless
Anaximander postulated an undifferentiated stuff out of which the world arose, which he called the Boundless, or apeiron. This stuff was not any of the traditional elements, earth, air (mist), fire, and water, but “something intermediate.” Because it was no more wet than dry and no more hot than cold, it was presumably damp and tepid. In opposition to Thales, who had held the basic stuff to be water, Anaximander conceived it as neutral, on the ground that the elements “are in opposition to one another—air is cold, water moist, fire hot—and therefore, if any one of them were infinite, the rest would have ceased to be by this time.” This is the first recorded philosophical argument, a criticism of a predecessor’s view supported by an appeal to reason rather than to revelation or to a special mode of insight.
The Boundless was supposed to be infinite in extent and “ageless and deathless,” that is, infinite in time. Anaximander called it “divine” but only because of its agelessness and deathlessness; he did not attribute to it any characteristics of personality or (as far as we know) intelligent consciousness.
The Boundless was also said to “encompass all the worlds,” implying an infinite or at least indefinitely large number of individual worlds like the one we inhabit. The initial step in the generation of a world occurs when as a result of its eternal motion (we are not told how) “something capable of begetting hot and cold out of the eternal is separated off.” The hot and the cold (conceived as things, not as qualities of a substance) separate, and at the same time, a motion in rotation is imparted to them. The hot, which is fire, encircles—”like the bark around a tree”—the cold, which contains earth, mist, and water. In due course, earth, mist, and water separate, the earth remaining at the center of the whirl, the water collecting in a ring around the earth, which is in turn enclosed in a circle of mist. The fire around the mist and water heats them until pressure builds up and, combined with the centrifugal force of the whirl, results in a cosmic explosion. The mist causes the fire to be contained in gigantic hoops, resembling inner tubes, that circle around the earth.
Anaximander’s Cosmology
The earth in Anaximander’s cosmology is shaped like a drum, the diameter being three times as great as the depth. Human beings live on one of the flat surfaces. Though supported by nothing, the earth remains at the center “because of its equal distance from everything.” The surface of the earth, which was at first entirely submerged, is now partly dry, and it keeps getting drier through continued evaporation. “The sea is what is left of the original moisture. The fire has dried up most of it and turned the rest salt by scorching it.”
Fire-filled hoops of mist, at distances of eighteen and twenty-seven earth-radii, surround the earth and revolve around it. Each of these hoops has on its inner side one hole (“like the nozzle of a bellows,” or like the valve-hole of an inner tube) through which the fire shines. The hoop eighteen earth-radii out is the Moon; the outermost is the Sun. The diameter of the Sun—that is, of the opening in the sun-hoop—is as great as that of Earth. Eclipses and the Moon’s phases are explained as obstructions over the holes. (We are not told what blocks them.) The stars are the innermost hoops, presumably at a distance of nine earth-radii from the earth. Anaximander would understandably infer that they were the hoops nearest us, for otherwise the hoops of Sun and Moon ought to appear as black bands in the night sky; but these thin, faint star-hoops would not interfere with the greater lights of the Sun and Moon.
Even if Anaximander did not affirm the rotation of the earth, his model of the world contains two very important new ideas. One is that of an earth without material support. All earlier, and indeed many later, cosmologists thought themselves obliged to explain the earth’s fixity by providing supports. Anaximander, seeing that such shifts only moved the problem back a step or two without solving it, declared boldly that the earth stays at the center “because of its equal distance from everything.”
The other new idea is that of explanation in terms of a theory involving postulated entities. Anaximander certainly could not see the hoops; only the “breathing-holes” were visible. Why did Anaximander postulate the hoops, instead of the simpler and more commonsense conception of fiery spheres or discs? Ancient sources give no hint; however, Anaximander may have reasoned that heavy bodies near the earth tend to move toward the center of concentration of mass, that is, toward the center of the earth. The earth, being a very heavy body, should likewise move toward the greatest concentration of mass, if there is one. There appear to be at least two of these concentrations: the Sun and the Moon. Therefore, if the Sun and Moon are what they appear to be, Earth ought to move toward them (or they toward us). Because this does not happen, the earth must really be equidistant from these bodies, despite appearances. This condition could hold only if the bodies surround the earth symmetrically, that is, are hoops, of which only the “breathing-holes” are visible. The idea of mist wrapping up fire, which seems strange to us, was natural enough to Anaximander; lightning emerging from clouds easily suggests such a notion. We know that Anaximander explained lightning in some such way: “When the wind is shut up in a cloud and bursts forth violently, the tearing of the cloud makes the noise of thunder, and the rift gives the appearance of a flash.”
A Scientific Thinker
If this conjectural restoration of Anaximander’s reasoning is correct, then Anaximander grasped the essential nature of theoretical explanation: of a law or natural regularity holding universally (in this instance, gravitation) and accounting for or generalized from observation (falling bodies on the earth’s surface), leading to the hypothesis of unobserved entities (the hoops) in order to render other observed phenomena (the Sun and Moon not falling) consistent with the law. This is nine-tenths of “scientific method” as now understood. Had he devised (or admitted the necessity of) some test of the hoop hypothesis, he would have had the other tenth. Even if he did not reason in this way, it seems that the hoops must have played this role of hypothetical entities in respect to some general theory, for there was no traditional or mythological incentive for supposing them. In consequence, the scientific nature of Anaximander’s thought is established.
An Evolutionary Theory
The power and originality of Anaximander’s thought are displayed preeminently in his biology. Mythmaking, even when it assumed a development of the cosmos as a whole, always conceived of animals, including humans, as having appeared on the scene from nowhere, in their latter-day forms, either as special creations of the gods or in some unexplained manner. In sharp contrast to this sort of facile storytelling, Anaximander worked out a theory of animal evolution based on the ideas of adaptation to environment and survival of the fittest.
His starting point was the observation that “while other animals quickly find food by themselves, man alone requires a lengthy period of suckling. Hence, had he been originally as he is now, he would never have survived.” That is to say, a theory of the world that in general is evolutionary is incompatible with the human species having appeared all at once (possibly as babies), for if it had, the species could never have survived in the “state of nature.” It follows that animals whose young are long immature must be the products of gradual development (presumably including socialization) from some other kind of life not so ill-fitted for the world.
Furthermore, the theory that in the beginning there had been no dry land suggested, if it did not require, that all life originated in the sea. Hence “living creatures arose from the moist element as it was evaporated by the sun.” The transition from marine to terrestrial life occurred thus: “The first animals were produced in the moisture, each enclosed in a prickly bark. As they advanced in age, they came out upon the drier part. When the bark broke off, they survived for a short time.” As for human beings, they too were “like other animals, namely fish, in the beginning. . . . At first human beings arose in the inside of fishes, and after having been reared like sharks, and become capable of protecting themselves, they were finally cast ashore and took to land.” The mention of sharks was not fanciful but based on the observation that certain sharks of the eastern Mediterranean hatch their eggs inside their bodies, which makes them seem akin to mammals.
The Father of Scientific Rationalism
Anaximander wrote a book, the Western world’s first scientific treatise, of which one sentence, or part of a sentence, has been preserved: Things return to their origins “as is ordained; for they give satisfaction and reparation to one another for their injustice according to the ordering of time.” It is clear from this that Anaximander’s philosophy made use of the concept of justice, pervasive in Greek thought, according to which there is an impersonal and inexorable force in nature charged with keeping things balanced. In society and in the world at large, every person, state, and element has its allotted portion, and “injustice,” the encroachment of anything beyond its bounds, is followed automatically and surely by restorative retribution. The notion lies at the root both of Greek moral ideas and the conception of “laws of nature”; in the fragment of Anaximander it is evidently being developed in the direction of the latter. It would be risky to infer anything more as to Anaximander’s worldview from this half sentence. In particular, it by no means shows that Anaximander viewed the universe as “inherently moral” in any sense that we would naturally give to that expression.
Even allowing for the fact that in Greek and other Near Eastern thought before the sixth century b.c.e. there existed a discernible tendency toward “rationalization” of traditional myths, and that the myths themselves contained the kernels of evolutionary and natural-law concepts, it is hardly an exaggeration to say that Anaximander single-handedly invented science and philosophy as we know them. Above all, he put rationalism on such a firm foundation that, among the educated, it took mythology a thousand years to overthrow it; and even then it did not perish utterly.
Any naturalistic worldview at the beginning of the sixth century b.c.e. would be remarkable; it is staggering to find that the very first philosophy contained such transcendently important ideas as an unsupported earth, theoretical explanation involving inferred entities, and animal evolution from marine organisms to humans in accordance with a principle of adaptation—and, quite possibly, the earth’s rotation and “gravitation” in addition.
It is not surprising that Anaximander’s immediate successor, Anaximenes, was incapable of such daring speculation. He accordingly taught a more “commonsense” philosophy in which the earth was held up by “mist,” the unobservable hoops were abolished, and the Sun, Moon, and stars were “like fiery leaves,” floating in the air. He was, so to speak, the first positivist. The belief that the earth needed a support continued to be held in Anaximander’s homeland for a century, down to and including Anaxagoras. However, at first, the Pythagoreans adopted Anaximander’s astronomy, hoops and all. Later, scientists Nicolaus Copernicus and Johannes Kepler were strongly influenced by Pythagorean theories. Unfortunately Anaximander’s equally promising beginnings in biology bore no fruit. Though Empedocles also recognized the principle of adaptation, the details of his evolutionary theory were fantastic; and after his time, the authority of Aristotle in favor of fixity of species put an end to evolutionary speculation in the ancient world; its revival two thousand years later owed nothing to Anaximander.
Principal Ideas Advanced
•The universe arose out of an infinite Boundless—a mass of undifferentiated material.
•The basic material of the universe was none of the elements (earth, air, fire, water), but something intermediate.
•The world was generated when the hot and the cold were separated from the Boundless by its eternal motion.
•The earth is shaped like a drum and is surrounded by fire-filled hoops of mist with holes on their inner sides (the Sun, Moon, stars).
•Justice is achieved in nature by a process of a return of all things to their origins.
Bibliography
Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers. London: Routledge, 1993. This book includes a chapter on Anaximander, focusing on his evolutionary theory, his account of the stability of the earth, and his view of the apeiron, or the Boundless.
Brumbaugh, Robert S. The Philosophers of Greece. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1964. This volume contains a short chapter on Anaximander’s life and accomplishments. Emphasizes cartography and engineering. Includes a reproduction of the first map designed by Anaximander.
Burnet, John. Early Greek Philosophy. 4th ed. New York: Barnes and Noble Books, 1945. A detailed scholarly analysis of Anaximander’s thought in the context of comparisons with, and influences on, other pre-Socratic philosophers.
Guthrie, W. K. C. The Earlier Presocratics and the Pythagoreans. Vol. 1 in A History of Greek Philosophy. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1962. This is the best work to consult for a thorough, dependable, and readable overview of Anaximander’s philosophy. It focuses on Anaximander’s cosmology and his view of the apeiron.
Kahn, Charles H. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmology. New York: Columbia University Press, 1960. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1994. Surveys the documentary evidence for Anaximander’s views, reconstructs a detailed cosmology from documentary texts, and devotes an entire chapter to analysis and interpretation of Anaximander’s fragment.
Kirk, Geoffrey S., John E. Raven, and M. Schofield. The Presocratic Philosophers. 2d ed. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1983. One chapter contains a scholarly account of Anaximander’s philosophy; includes Greek text of his fragment and testimony.
Seligman, Paul. The Apeiron of Anaximander: A Study in the Origin and Function of Metaphysical Ideas. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1975. Originally the author’s University of London dissertation, this book includes numerous chapters focusing specifically on Anaximander’s view of the apeiron and the meaning and role of adikia (injustice). It presupposes no prior knowledge on reader’s part but is very scholarly and detailed in its examination of the texts.
Taylor, C. C. W., ed. From the Beginning to Plato. Vol. 1 in Routledge History of Philosophy. London: Routledge, 1997. Contains a chapter on the Ionian philosophers, in which Anaximander’s cosmology is examined. This section on Anaximander is brief, readable, and very accessible to the nonspecialist.
West, M. L. Early Greek Philosophy and the Orient. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971. Contains a substantial chapter examining Asian elements in the philosophy of both Anaximander and Anaximenes.
Wheelwright, Philip, ed. The Presocratics. New York: Macmillan, 1966. A primary source. Contains the Anaximander fragment in translation. Also contains testimonies from Aristotle and other Greek and Latin sources who read and commented on Anaximander’s treatise.